翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ James Octavius Machell
・ James Oddo
・ James Odongo
・ James of Aragon
・ James of Aragon (monk)
・ James of Avesnes
・ James of Brescia
・ James of Castile, Lord of Cameros
・ James of Ireland
・ James of Jülich
・ James of Lausanne
・ James of Majorca
・ James of Majorca (monk)
・ James of Manug
・ James of Mar, 30th Earl of Mar
James of Metz
・ James of Piedmont
・ James of Portugal
・ James of Saint George
・ James of Scotland
・ James of the Marches
・ James of Venice
・ James of Viterbo
・ James Ogden
・ James Ogilvie
・ James Ogilvie Fairlie
・ James Ogilvie-Grant, 11th Earl of Seafield
・ James Ogilvy
・ James Ogilvy (disambiguation)
・ James Ogilvy, 1st Earl of Airlie


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

James of Metz : ウィキペディア英語版
James of Metz
Very little is known about the life and times of James Metz. It is a mystery when he was born and when he died, but what is known is that he was philosophically active in the first decade of the fourteenth century. Of his works that survive presently, much of it remains unedited, and only a dozen manuscript copies still exist.〔Gracia, Jorge J.E., and Timothy B. Noone. A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Malden : Blackwell, 2003. 249-251.〕 James was known as a Dominican Theologian, which meant following the teachings of Saint Thomas Aquinas. However, James earned the reputation for being a "critical-Thomist,"〔Irribarren, Isabel. "Henry of Ghent's Teaching on Modes and its Influence in the Fourteenth Century." Mediaeval Studies. 64. Toronto : Pontificial Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 2002. Print.〕 as he openly disagreed some of Aquinas's positions. One account of James describes him as an “eclectic thinker,” and that his works were partially influenced by Peter of Auvergne as well as Henry of Ghent.〔Gracia, Jorge J.E., and Timothy B. Noone. A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Malden : Blackwell, 2003. 249-251.〕
==Philosophical==

The only philosophical work of James’s that is known for certain is that he gave two lectures on Peter Lombard’s ''Sentences''.〔Pasnau, Robert. The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2010. 899. Print.〕 Presumably, these lectures occurred at the University of Paris, roughly from 1300-1306. An instance in which James did not see eye-to-eye with Aquinas was in regard to the way Aquinas described individuation by matter. Aquinas held the view that that matter is the principle of individuation. James, on the other hand, believed that form is the principle of individuation.〔Gracia, Jorge J.E., and Timothy B. Noone. A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Malden : Blackwell, 2003. 249-251.〕 Another disagreement between James and Aquinas concerned the process of knowledge, primarily knowledge of immaterial substances and knowledge of God. James’s views differed from those of Aquinas in that James attempted to find compatibility between Augustinian and Aristotelian accounts of knowledge. These disagreements with Aquinas warranted criticism from the Master General of Dominican Order, Hervaeus Natalis, as he wrote a doctrine called "A Correction of Brother James Metz." 〔Brown, Stephen F., and Juan Carlos Flores. Historical Dictionary of Medieval Philosophy and Theology. 76. Toronto : The Scarecrow Press, Inc., 2007. 150-151. Print.〕 Concerning the divine essence, James held the view that it functioned as an origin, and that it “performs solely in relation to being.”〔Mojsisch, Burkhard. Meister Eckart: Analogy, Univocity, and Unity. Philadelphia: John Benjamins B.V., 2001. 113-16. Print.〕 James advocated that there is a duality to the divine essence. In one instance it is a pure essence, the sole origin of our act and our being. In the second instance, James believed essence can also be seen as an attribute, and that it is the cause of specific actions.

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「James of Metz」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.